Monday, August 29, 2016
Priviged Planet:. New Study Suggests We are Alone in the Cosmos
In the paper, the three astronomers calculated the likelihood for advanced life as a function of cosmic time and concluded that we humans must be the first on the cosmic scene. In their calculation, they presumed that any life possibly existing in the universe must be like us in that its chemistry is carbon-base ...
Click on the link below
Are We Alone in the Cosmos?
Saturday, August 27, 2016
Book Review: No God But One by Nabeel Qureshi
Book Review: No God But One: A Former Muslim Investigates the Evidence For Islam & Christianity
Posted by Clark Bates
August 27, 2016
For
those familiar with his previous writings, Nabeel Qureshi's biography
as a Muslim Zealot turned Christian apologist has made him the
overnight authority on Christian/Islamic Apologetics.
As he recounted in his first work Seeking Allah, Finding
Jesus, Nabeel spent much of his
life as a devout American Muslim, fervently seeking to spread the
faith of Allah and his messenger Muhammad to all who would hear him.
Raised to love Islam but faced with insurmountable questions after
the events of 9/11, the author sought to investigate his faith and
silence the doubts that began to permeate his thoughts and worship.
Through multiple interactions with Christians and Muslims, over the
course of four years, Nabeel's faith in Allah and the Prophet began
to erode, while his realization and acceptance of Jesus began to
increase. As he recalls,
“On
August 24, 2005, when I could resist no longer, I bent my knee to
Jesus and proclaimed my faith in Him. Soon after my family was
shattered, and the next year of my life was by far the most
harrowing I have ever endured. I was now an outsider, both to my
family and to all my friends in the Islamic community.”1
Having achieved a degree in medicine from Eastern Virginia Medical
School, the author focused his sights on defense of the Christian
faith, earning degrees in apologetics from Biola University and
religion from Duke. Currently, Nabeel is pursuing his doctorate in
New Testament studies from Oxford University and is an international
speaker for Ravi Zacharias International Ministries. The events that
Nabeel describes in his premier writing are now parlayed into his
latest work as a structured, point-by-point comparison of the
Christian and Islamic faiths, with the ultimate goal of demonstrating
the overwhelming reliability of Christianity and the need for Muslims
worldwide to seek the truth.
Separated
into ten parts, No God but One
addresses the various dissimilarities between the two faiths,
followed by an epistemological analysis of each faith's claim to
truth. Much of Nabeel's writing is contemporary with the debates
circulating in the public sphere regarding Muslims and Christians
worshiping the same God, the comparison of modern jihad with that of
the Crusades, Muhammad as opposed to Jesus, the evidence for the
resurrection of Christ, and the Quranic claims of divine origin and
perfection. In so doing, the author provides a plethora of
information for the Christian and Muslim reader, sandwiched between
the harrowing account of a young Muslim girl's conversion to
Christianity and its resulting consequences.
Nabeel's method of approach creates a means by which the reader is
systematically exposed to an increasingly monumental level of
evidence, calling into question the very foundations of Islam. The
author crafts arguments that include comparing and contrasting Sharia
versus the Gospel, Jesus versus Muhammed, Trinity versus Tawhid
(Allah is absolutely one), and the Quran versus the Bible. All the
while interspersing his own personal life story into the content of
each comparison, Nabeel provides the reader with an immersive
experience that relates audience to narrator on an intimate level
rather than merely offering data for consumption.
Nabeel's earlier work, Answering Jihad, suffered slightly
from a sense of hurried compilation. Admittedly, that work was
produced within the period of a few months, but impressively carried
a great deal of information. No God but One does not suffer
from this in any way. From start to finish one gets the impression
that great care and compassion has gone into each chapter. The
author's desire to present his own journey to faith as the template
upon which each challenge is made allows the reader to feel for those
embracing the Islamic faith and long for them to see truth. As
Nabeel states at the outset, “In rejecting the Source of Life, we
bring death upon ourselves. This bears repeating: The result of sin
is death because it is a rejection of the Source of Life.”2
However emotionally effective this text may be, it does not remain
at a superficial level. In dealing with the relation of Islamic
Tawhid versus the Trinity, the author relays, both through his
firsthand knowledge and investigative results, that, “the trinity
the Quran is denying is actually tri-theism, three gods: Allah,
Jesus, and Mary.”3
Challenging not only the logical difficulties that arise from the
Islamic doctrine of Tawhid, namely the teaching that Allah can
have no attributes and remain Tawhid, Nabeel turns the Islamic
argument of Allah's transcendence on it's head, accusing Islam of
creating a god made in the image of man: “If God created our minds,
then He must be greater than their comprehension. Who are we to
demand that He be simple enough for us to understand Him?”4
The purpose of this book seems very clear, the faith of Islam cannot
overcome the historical data and metaphysical claims upon which it
survives. In contrast, the Christian faith is built upon
metaphysical truth claims, grounded in the historical space-time
event of the resurrection. In every avenue of inquisition the author
finds Islam untenable and Christianity unwavering. However, his
earnest desire to not abandon the faith of his birth reminds readers
that this debate involves real people in desperate spiritual
circumstances. Far from being a tool by which to browbeat
non-Christians, Nabeel's book seeks to build empathy while
simultaneously conveying truth.
The target audience of this book is broad. It's readability makes it
accessible to every layperson of either faith. At the same time,
it's detailed information provides an excellent apologetic resource
for the pastor, teacher or evangelist seeking to reach out to their
Islamic neighbors or friends. While some Christians might find the
apologetic used within to be cursory, so too might the skilled
Muslim; however, for many of both worldviews a deep understanding of
their faith's cardinal doctrines seems to be sincerely lacking in the
West, and, as such, this book will continue to serve even them. This
work may stand out as the author's crowning achievement, but it is
too soon to be certain. As far as effectively conveying the reason
for Christianity over Islam, Nabeel succeeds admirably. Doing so in
a manner that engenders no hostility from the side of the writer is
an even greater achievement, and is one that is successfully
accomplished as well. As the author expresses it in his appeal to
Muslim brothers and sisters, “Leaving Islam can cost you
everything: family, friends, job, everything you have ever known, and
maybe even life itself. Is it really worth sacrificing everything
for the truth? The answer is simple: It depends on the value of
truth.”5
1Nabeel
Qureshi, No God but One:A Former Muslim Investigates the Evidence
for Islam & Christianity,
(Grand Rapids: Zondervan, 2016), 23.
2Nabeel
Qureshi, No God but One, 34.
3Ibid.,
62.
4Ibid.,
68.
5Ibid.,
349.
Tuesday, August 23, 2016
A Brief Defense of the Moral Argument
Posted by Clark Bates
August, 23, 2016
What moral difference would it make if God did not exist? A large
portion of society today would probably say, “None.” An
excellent example of this is found in the U.N. Declaration of Human
Rights. It says:
“All human beings are born free and equal in dignity and rights.
They are endowed with reason and conscience and should act towards
one another in a spirit of brotherhood.”
Now compare this with the U.S. Declaration of Independence:
“We hold these truths to be self-evident that all men are created
equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain
unalienable rights, among these are life, liberty, and the pursuit of
happiness.”
The point of agreement within these two worldviews is the objective
value of humanity, but the area of discord is the source of this
value. According to the U.N., objective moral value presumably comes
by naturalistic processes. Humans are simply “born with it.”
Whereas the Declaration of Independence asserts that this objective
moral value comes from something greater, namely God.
This is the heart of the Moral Argument for God. Formally stated it
would sound like this:
- If objective moral values exist, then God exists.
- Objective moral values do exist.
- Therefore, God exists.
On the basis of this argument naturalism cannot account for objective
moral values, such as those stated in the U.N. Declaration of Human
Rights, because naturalism functions as a valueless process. The
same naturalism that Tennyson called “Red in tooth and claw,” and
that Richard Dawkins said in , “should not be used as a guide for
society”, is a valueless process that cannot conceivably produce
valuable personal beings.1
2
Let's examine each premise to see if the conclusion follows:
Premise
1: If Objective Moral Values Exist, God Exists.
Now
the only way to determine if this premise is true is if it can be
demonstrated that naturalism cannot produce moral values and duties.
Let's begin by defining what I mean by an objective moral value or
duty. An objective moral value or duty is a an obligation to do what
is right in a given circumstance regardless of one's personal
opinion. It's often asserted that many atheists or non-theists are
just as, if not more than, moral as Christians. This is used as
evidence that belief in God is not necessary for morality to exist.
This is absolutely true. You don't have to believe that God exists
in order to be moral. But the argument before us is not that it is
necessary to believe
in God for objective moral values and duties to exist, but that for
objective moral values and duties to exist God must exist. It has
nothing to do with whether or not one believes in God, for all
mankind is created with the same image of God regardless of their
belief system and therefore all mankind is able to recognize the same
objective moral standards.
According to Sam Harris, “If there are psychological laws that
govern human well-being, knowledge of these laws would provide an
enduring basis of objective morality.”
3 What Harris is proposing is a form of “atheistic realism” which asserts both that the physical universe is all that is and yet objective moral values are brute facts that exist within it. The issue here is that what he's asserting is that metaphysical realities somehow exist within a strictly physical world and we should just not question that. To take it a step further, a moral obligation is a type of proposition, i.e. “Rape is bad.” We make propositions all the time, but they arise from our mind; Harris is insisting that these objective propositions somehow arise from mindlessness. This is a kind of expansion on the work of another atheist named Michael Martin who wrote that “One could affirm the objective immorality of rape and deny the existence of God with perfect consistency.” In both instances these men are making the claim that moral values and duties are just the result of human evolutionary development, however they are guilty of equivocating what “is” with what “ought” to be. It “is” true that mankind psychologically acknowledges laws (that exist apart from themselves mind you) that provide an enduring basis of reality. It “is” true that one can affirm that rape is wrong and deny God, but neither of these factors can answer “why” those things are true. They tell us that rape “is” wrong, but not why rape “ought” to be wrong. They confuse an is with an ought.
3 What Harris is proposing is a form of “atheistic realism” which asserts both that the physical universe is all that is and yet objective moral values are brute facts that exist within it. The issue here is that what he's asserting is that metaphysical realities somehow exist within a strictly physical world and we should just not question that. To take it a step further, a moral obligation is a type of proposition, i.e. “Rape is bad.” We make propositions all the time, but they arise from our mind; Harris is insisting that these objective propositions somehow arise from mindlessness. This is a kind of expansion on the work of another atheist named Michael Martin who wrote that “One could affirm the objective immorality of rape and deny the existence of God with perfect consistency.” In both instances these men are making the claim that moral values and duties are just the result of human evolutionary development, however they are guilty of equivocating what “is” with what “ought” to be. It “is” true that mankind psychologically acknowledges laws (that exist apart from themselves mind you) that provide an enduring basis of reality. It “is” true that one can affirm that rape is wrong and deny God, but neither of these factors can answer “why” those things are true. They tell us that rape “is” wrong, but not why rape “ought” to be wrong. They confuse an is with an ought.
To put it another way, the evolutionary process is primarily
interested in survival, not in true belief. It can, and has been,
argued that moral values help us survive, but this says nothing about
whether those moral values are true, and for morality to be objective
it must necessarily be true. We may believe, with the UN, that human
beings have intrinsic value and that this has helped us survive, but
this may still be false. We may believe in moral obligations as a
means of preservation of the species, but this belief may be wrong.
And if an appeal to objective moral values is going to be made, such
an appeal requires that these values not only be real, but that they
be true. For if they are not true, there is no longer an objective
reason to abide by them. If naturalism fails to account for the
“Why” of objective moral values and duties it cannot serve as
adequate explanation for them.
Premise 2: Objective Moral Values do Exist
The nihilist Friedrich Nietzsche famously, and rather dramatically,
stated that “God is dead” in his “Parable of the Madman”, but
even he recognized that with the destruction of God came the
destruction of objective value. He wrote in that same parable,
"How shall we comfort ourselves, the murderers of all murderers?
What was holiest and mightiest of all that the world has yet owned
has bled to death under our knives: who will wipe this blood off us?
What water is there for us to clean ourselves? What festivals of
atonement, what sacred games shall we have to invent? Is not the
greatness of this deed too great for us? Must we ourselves not become
gods simply to appear worthy of it?”4
The existentialist Jean-Paul Sartre saw this too when he wrote,
“It is very distressing that God does not exist, because all
possibility of finding values in a heaven of ideas disappears along
with Him.”5
Now it's often claimed that objective morality cannot exist given
the wide diversity of moral values throughout the world. However,
C.S. Lewis, in his work The Abolition of Man, surveyed the
basic moral precepts of various cultures and found at least 8 points
of commonality with all. There were agreed upon moral laws regarding
general and special benevolence, or kindness, an expected moral duty
towards parents and the elderly, moral laws regarding justice,
regarding integrity and truth, regarding mercy and generosity. In
short, while differences in particular moral circumstances may exist
in various cultures, there are multiple areas of cross-cultural
common morality. As Frank Turek rather comically reiterates, Hindus
believe that it is immoral to eat cows, whereas Americans do not.
The reason that Hindus find it immoral to eat cattle is their belief
in re-incarnation and the potential for that cow to be inhabited by
an ancestor. Americans eat cows because we don't believe that
Grandma is in the cow. However, while the practice is different the
moral value remains the same, both Americans and Hindus agree, it's
wrong to eat Grandma!
While it might be en vogue to deny the existence of an objective
moral law, it is impossible to live consistently with that belief.
Our daily lives belie the reality of objective moral values. Our
reactions to perceived violations reveal a sense of moral justice.
You might say that you don't believe in an objective moral standard
but if you've ever been the victim of theft or been in a hit and run
accident you've filed a police report! You did this because you
intrinsically acknowledge that it is morally objectionable for
someone else to take your belongings or for someone to damage your
car without retribution.
Without an objective moral law there would be no standard for human
rights. Just as we've seen in the U.S. Declaration of Independence,
human rights are endowed by the Creator, making them unalienable,
that is to say, inherent. When Nazi war criminals were brought
before the Nuremburg trials they were convicted of violating human
rights inherent to all people. If moral values and duties were
merely subjective, the Nazis did nothing wrong. For them, the
extermination of various races and people was the morally right
action to achieve the Ubermensch (Supermen). The Allied
nations could not accuse them of committing criminal actions unless a
standard of moral values and duties exists beyond personal
preference. What's more, any moment we as individuals or as a
society declare one particular set of moral values deficient to
another, we are claiming to know a standard by which they are
measured.
Let me ask you this, “Why do Black Lives Matter?” I don't ask
that to be inflammatory. I agree that black lives do matter, but
unless you have some objective moral standard by which to determine
that they matter, there's nothing to protest. The sense of social
injustice that we see rising up in various areas of this country
point to the recognition of a universal standard of human value.
Ironically, the political group that most often denies the existence
of objective morality yet vociferously supports social justice
movements are labeled “progressives”. The very name of which
implies that a change in moral values must occur, meaning we are not
living up to an unspecified objective moral standard that is claimed
to not exist.
Truth can be defined in many cases as that which best corresponds to
reality. Objective moral values surface in every facet of our daily
lives, bleeding through the reality of our existence. When someone
consistently maintains a belief despite its being contradicted by
what is generally accepted as reality it's called being delusional.
No matter how loudly one might shout down the existence of objective
moral values or duties, the truth of reality will always prove them
wrong.
Which brings us to:
Premise 3: Therefore, God exists
In the absence of a naturalistic
explanation for objective moral values and the verifiable existence
of these same objective moral values, the explanation must exist
beyond the realm of naturalism. The fact that moral values are
equivalent to moral propositions means that they must be made by a
moral mind that transcends our own in such a way that all of humanity
can perceive it. In the same manner that physical laws cannot be
asserted without being applied by a lawgiver, neither can moral law
be acknowledged without a Moral Lawgiver. This Mind or Lawgiver is
best understood as God. The rejection of such a possibility finds
its existential bite in the accountability that necessarily follows.
If there is a moral standard to which we are held, set by a
transcendent Moral Lawgiver, then we are accountable to that
Lawgiver. As C.S. Lewis wrote in Mere
Christianity,
“It is after you have realized that there is a Moral Law and a
Power behind the law, and that you have broken that law and put
yourself wrong with that Power – it is after all this, and not a
moment sooner, that Christianity begins to talk.”6
1Alfred
Lord Tennyson, In Memoriam A.H.H.,
Canto 56,
“Who
trusted God was love indeed
And love Creation's final law
And love Creation's final law
Tho' Nature, red in tooth and claw
With ravine, shriek'd against his creed.”
With ravine, shriek'd against his creed.”
2Richard
Dawkins, The Selfish Gene,
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016), 380-1.
3Sam
Harris, The Moral Landscape: How Science can Determine Human
Values, (Simon & Schuster,
2011), 215.
4Friedrich
Nietzsche, “The Parable of the Madman”
5Jean
Paul-Sartre, “Existentialism is a Humanism,” trans. Bernard
Frechtman, (Carol Publishing Group, 1945).
6C.S>
Lewis, Mere Christianity,
(Grand Rapids: Zondervan, 2001), 31.
Saturday, August 6, 2016
Who Wrote the Book of . . . 1 Peter?
Posted by Clark Bates
August, 6, 2016
Having
discussed the contested books of Paul and the authorship of the
gospels, this series on New Testament authorship will now turn toward
the writings of Peter. It may or may not surprise some readers to
hear that both epistles that bear the apostle Peter's name are highly
questioned, and in many cases, considered pseudonymous. This belief
has arisen from the school of source criticism that gained prominence
in the late nineteenth and early twentieth century, but recent
scholarship has begun to demonstrate the inability of these
conclusion to truly account for the authorship of the Petrine
epistles.
It
has been the format of this series to present the case against
traditional authorship, followed by a parallel case for it. I have
decided that for this article and perhaps the next, the format will
be more amalgamated in which each objection to traditional authorship
will be challenged immediately. We will then conclude with a brief
summary and discussion on additional evidence for the Petrine
authorship of this epistle.
Who
wrote 1 Peter?
This
question is, of course, the heart of the entire article, but given
that 1 Peter begins with a salutation attributed to the apostle
himself (1:1) it becomes glaringly important. The nature of
pseudonymity has been discussed in earlier articles on Paul and will
not be regurgitated here, but it has become a prevalent opinion with
many modern scholars to accept authorship of this epistle by a
Petrine group in Rome between AD 75 and 95, seeking to accurately
represent the apostle's thoughts.1
For those that embrace a late dating to the book, the existence of
such a group would be inevitable from a sociological standpoint, but
even if this were a sociological inevitability, it does not explain
why such a group would write in such a way.
By
way of example, both in the letter's opening and close, references
are made to Mark and Silvanus (1:1; 5:12-13). Are these to be
understood as pseudonymous fiction? If this epistle were carried by
Silvanus, as has been suggested, how was he to represent the letter
to its recipients, knowing it was a forgery? Even if we are to
accept that the Gospel according to Mark is Peter's testimony, the
author of the gospel does not presume to write it in the apostle's
name. Perhaps more importantly, while a Petrine group of faithful
followers might present an attractive alternative, there is no extant
evidence from the first century that such a group ever existed.
Major
Challenges to Traditional Authorship
Almost
all modern challenges to apostolic authorship can be contained within
4 categories: 1. The Greek of the epistle is to advanced for the
apostle Peter; 2. The content of the book reflects a church
structure and social environment that corresponds to a time decades
after the apostle's lifetime; 3. The epistle reflects a dependence
on the deutero-Pauline letters (those letters contested as
pseudonymous in their own right) making its dating to be after them
and thus beyond Peter's lifetime; and 4. Christianity could not have
reached the remote areas of Asia Minor spoken of in the letter and
become a target of major persecution until a decade after Peter had
died.
Taking
each of these objections in turn, it must be acknowledged that the
Greek of 1 Peter does appear to be of a higher quality than one would
expect from a fisherman-turned-apostle. Most who support the earlier
dating of this authorship will at least propose the use of a
considerably more skilled Greek amanuensis. That being said, quality
of language can be, to some extent, subjective. The letter is argued
to have such features as, “polished Attic style, Classical
vocabulary . . . and rhetorical quality. . . mak[ing] it one of the
more refined writings in the NT.”2
But the question persists as to whether such language and style
require
an author formally trained in Greek, and whether or not the apostle
Peter could have attained such skill in his lifetime.
It has recently been noted that, within the syntax of the epistle, 1 Peter exhibits a clearly bilingual interference, consistent with a Semitic author for whom Greek is a second language.3 “This is perhaps the most telling feature of the Greek in 1 Peter, for a letter's syntax flows almost subconsciously from an author's proficiency with the language. . .”4 When the syntax of 1 Peter is paralleled with that of another Semitic author like Josephus we find that rather than demonstrating refined Greek understanding, the author was deficient to Josephus in multiple areas, including use of prepositions, genitive personal pronouns and the dative case with the preposition en. What this demonstrates is that the author of the epistle was likely of Semitic origin (thus limited to the area of Palestine) in the first century. He would not have been a Greek or Latin speaking Roman or from Asia Minor, making the pseudonymous authorship by a Petrine group less likely.
The
second argument against apostolic authorship is based on the
addressed persecution and church structure of 1 Peter. Three
emperors of note instituted Christian persecution in the Roman empire
during the first century: Nero (54-68), Domitian (81-96), and Trajan
(98-117). The nature of persecution in the book is far too vague to
be used as a method of dating however. When examining the letter
itself, the persecution listed appears to be limited to malicious
talk, verbal slander, and false accusations (1:6; 2:12, 15: 3:9, 16;
4:12, 16). This form of persecution need not necessarily point to
the level of martyrdom seen under the emperors mentioned and could
easily refer to a time period prior to the escalation of government
sanctioned and enforced persecution.
The
historian Pliny the Younger wrote approximately 60 letters tot he
emperor Trajan over a three year period in AD 90, some of which
concerned the persistent problem of Christianity. In these letters
he recounted Christians abdicating their faith twenty years prior.5
If what is written in 1 Peter regards a less dire situation than
that of Pliny then it must be written more than twenty years prior.
Much of the debate around the persecutions centers on the “fiery
ordeal” of 1 Peter 4:12. Those who claim t a late dating see this
as a reference to Nero who used Christians as living torches to light
the streets of Rome at night, but recent scholarship suggests this is
more likely am acknowledgment to the philosopher Seneca, a
contemporary of Peter, who wrote, “Fire tests gold, affliction
tests strong men.”6
The image of trials as a testing analogous to fire smelting gold is
characteristic of the epistle (1:7, 18; 4:12). Peter describes the
trial as worldwide (5:9), which suggests a persecution faced by all
Christians, not one executed by Roman officials in one place.
This
type of persecution was common in the early church.7
Most who hold to a pseudonymous authorship maintain that the letter
was written after AD 70 but prior to the reign of Domitian. This is
based on 1 Peter 4:15-16 which suggests that Christians were being
arrested simply for being Christians, as though it were akin to a
common thief, something argued to be impossible prior to Nero.8
Regarding
the church structure, it is stated that the use of the term
episkopountes
(overseeing) in 5:2 refers to the monarchical bishop of the second
century. Given the history of this term, the above challenge is more
of a case of reading a second century reality backward into the text.
As far back as the book of Acts, the apostle Paul uses presbyteroi
(elders) and episkopoi
interchangeably. In Acts 20:17 and 28 the apostle exhorts the
Ephesian elders (presbyteroi)
to shepherd (promainein)
the people of God because they are overseers (episkopoi)!
There is clearly no distinction of terms here, nor any suggestion of
official offices. Given that 1 Peter is not written tot a local
body, but to a wide area likely covering a territory that would
surpass a single bishop there is no reason to assume the later
meaning is applied to the term here.
Coming
finally to the epistle's dependence on deutero-Pauline literature.
First, it must be recognized that this claim assumes the pseudonymity
of those letters, which is not a certainty. Second, the argument has
been adjusted simply to 1 Peter's dependency on Paul the apostle as
well. Even to assume this dependency would be to suggest a
pseudonymous author from a Pauline school rather than a Petrine one,
but this creates the added question of why this letter would not then
be attributed to Paul instead of Peter? Some have sought to avoid
this difficulty by explaining the dependence as an amalgamation of of
Petrine and Pauline traditions in which “much Pauline tradition is
now set forth under the name of Peter”, the assumed primary apostle
of Rome.9
This view struggles some, first in its assumption that Peter was in
a position of hegemony in the early church beyond that of other
apostles, and second this must be assumed to have consistently
developed within twenty years of his death.
Notwithstanding
these objections, Peter makes no reference to Paul or his letters in
this epistle, and similarities that do exist are of terms and themes
that could be less reliant on Paul and more understandably based upon
a common faith and Christian tradition. The connection between the
two apostles is strained. Too strained even to be a reliable
objection to traditional authorship.
Secondary
Support for Traditional Authorship
A
final note on pseudonymity must be mentioned. While the prevalence
of pseudepigraphy has already been discussed, such writings were
largely connected to certain genres. Primarily wisdom literature
(Wisdom of Solomon) and apocalyptic (1 Enoch). 1 Peter is neither of
these and the acceptance of pseudonymous letters as a genre is
contestable. To argue that the book is pseudonymous while retaining
a direct link to apostolic authority (as is often claimed) is
unverifiable when the link can only be inferred, and merely consists
of an attempt to remain skeptical while retaining some sense of
authority.
However, even a motive of honoring the apostle by way of pseudonymity finds no support in the first century. In fact, it is quite the opposite. The spurious letter of 3 Corinthians, attributed to Paul, enjoyed acceptance until it was recognized as being non-Pauline. When a presbyter of Asia Minor was discovered as its author, he was not congratulated but censured and removed from church office.
However, even a motive of honoring the apostle by way of pseudonymity finds no support in the first century. In fact, it is quite the opposite. The spurious letter of 3 Corinthians, attributed to Paul, enjoyed acceptance until it was recognized as being non-Pauline. When a presbyter of Asia Minor was discovered as its author, he was not congratulated but censured and removed from church office.
Lastly,
the epistle of 1 Peter contains several allusions to the teachings of
Jesus. While the value of these allusions in determining authorship
is debated, the list ranges from thirty to at least fifteen. These
verba
Christi, as
they are known, parallel teachings found in all four Gospels, but do
not quote the Gospels which does not indicate a literary dependence
but one of experience. On this topic, Gundry writes, “The most
striking feature about the verba
Christi
in 1 Peter, however, is that they refer to contexts in the gospels
which are especially associated with the apostle Peter.”10
Conclusion
While
more could be said regarding the geography of the intended recipients
of this epistle, and even the theology within its text, sufficient is
the discussion at this stage to close. As has been seen in may of
the earlier articles, source-criticism has always sought to
understand New Testament literature from a vantage point of
skepticism. While this is not necessarily inappropriate, the result,
as we see here, is too often one in which the critic will maintain
skepticism even in light of insufferable difficulties. It is not a
position of integrity to assert a skeptical position solely on the
basis of group think or an unwillingness to admit previous error.
The evidence must always lead those investigating to a conclusion,
wherever it may lead. In the case of New Testament authorship, what
we often see is a magnifying of contrary evidence against authorship
and a diminishing of evidence for. However, when the data is
objectively analyzed the traditional authorship rises above
accusations as the more likely at best or inconclusive at worst.
1J.K.
Elliott, Essays and Studies in the New Testament Textual
Criticism, (Cordoba: Ediciones
el Amendro, 1992), 127-30.
2Elliott,
ESNTTC, 120.
3Karen
H. Jobes, Baker Exegetical Commentary on the New Testament: 1
Peter, (Grand Rapids: Baker
Academic, 2005), 7.
4Jobes,
1 Peter, 7.
5Pliny
the Younger, Letters,
10.96.6.
6Seneca,
On Providence, 5.10.
71
Thess.1:6; 2:14-16; 3:3-5; Matt. 10:16-20; Gal. 4:29.
8L.
Goppelt, A Commentary on 1 Peter,
trans. J.E. Alsup, (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1993), 39-45.
9M.E.
Boring, Abingdon New Testament Commentary Series: 1 Peter,
(Nashville: Abingdon, 1999), 43.
10R.
H. Gundry, “Verba Christi in 1 Peter: Their Implications
Concerning the Authorship of 1 Peter and the Authenticity of the
Gospel Tradition,” New Testament Studies,
13 (1966-67), 349.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)